We consider the system Applicative_05__Ex5Folding. Alphabet: 0 : [] --> c add : [] --> a -> c -> c cons : [a * b] --> b fold : [a -> c -> c * c] --> b -> c mul : [] --> a -> c -> c nil : [] --> b plus : [c * c] --> c prod : [] --> b -> c s : [c] --> c sum : [] --> b -> c times : [c * c] --> c Rules: fold(f, x) nil => x fold(f, x) cons(y, z) => f y (fold(f, x) z) plus(0, x) => x plus(s(x), y) => s(plus(x, y)) times(0, x) => 0 times(s(x), y) => plus(times(x, y), y) sum => fold(add, 0) prod => fold(mul, s(0)) This AFS is converted to an AFSM simply by replacing all free variables by meta-variables (with arity 0). We observe that the rules contain a first-order subset: plus(0, X) => X plus(s(X), Y) => s(plus(X, Y)) times(0, X) => 0 times(s(X), Y) => plus(times(X, Y), Y) Moreover, the system is orthogonal. Thus, by [Kop12, Thm. 7.55], we may omit all first-order dependency pairs from the dependency pair problem (DP(R), R) if this first-order part is terminating when seen as a many-sorted first-order TRS. According to the external first-order termination prover, this system is indeed terminating: || proof of resources/system.trs || # AProVE Commit ID: d84c10301d352dfd14de2104819581f4682260f5 fuhs 20130616 || || || Termination w.r.t. Q of the given QTRS could be proven: || || (0) QTRS || (1) QTRSRRRProof [EQUIVALENT] || (2) QTRS || (3) RisEmptyProof [EQUIVALENT] || (4) YES || || || ---------------------------------------- || || (0) || Obligation: || Q restricted rewrite system: || The TRS R consists of the following rules: || || plus(0, %X) -> %X || plus(s(%X), %Y) -> s(plus(%X, %Y)) || times(0, %X) -> 0 || times(s(%X), %Y) -> plus(times(%X, %Y), %Y) || || Q is empty. || || ---------------------------------------- || || (1) QTRSRRRProof (EQUIVALENT) || Used ordering: || Quasi precedence: || times_2 > plus_2 > s_1 || times_2 > 0 > s_1 || || || Status: || plus_2: multiset status || 0: multiset status || s_1: multiset status || times_2: multiset status || || With this ordering the following rules can be removed by the rule removal processor [LPAR04] because they are oriented strictly: || || plus(0, %X) -> %X || plus(s(%X), %Y) -> s(plus(%X, %Y)) || times(0, %X) -> 0 || times(s(%X), %Y) -> plus(times(%X, %Y), %Y) || || || || || ---------------------------------------- || || (2) || Obligation: || Q restricted rewrite system: || R is empty. || Q is empty. || || ---------------------------------------- || || (3) RisEmptyProof (EQUIVALENT) || The TRS R is empty. Hence, termination is trivially proven. || ---------------------------------------- || || (4) || YES || We use the dependency pair framework as described in [Kop12, Ch. 6/7], with dynamic dependency pairs. After applying [Kop12, Thm. 7.22] to denote collapsing dependency pairs in an extended form, we thus obtain the following dependency pair problem (P_0, R_0, minimal, formative): Dependency Pairs P_0: 0] fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z) =#> F(Y, fold(F, X) Z) 1] fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z) =#> fold(F, X) Z 2] fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z) =#> fold#(F, X) 3] sum X =#> fold(add, 0) X 4] sum# =#> fold#(add, 0) 5] prod X =#> fold(mul, s(0)) X 6] prod# =#> fold#(mul, s(0)) Rules R_0: fold(F, X) nil => X fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z) => F Y (fold(F, X) Z) plus(0, X) => X plus(s(X), Y) => s(plus(X, Y)) times(0, X) => 0 times(s(X), Y) => plus(times(X, Y), Y) sum => fold(add, 0) prod => fold(mul, s(0)) Thus, the original system is terminating if (P_0, R_0, minimal, formative) is finite. We consider the dependency pair problem (P_0, R_0, minimal, formative). We place the elements of P in a dependency graph approximation G (see e.g. [Kop12, Thm. 7.27, 7.29], as follows: * 0 : 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 * 1 : 0, 1, 2 * 2 : * 3 : 0, 1, 2 * 4 : * 5 : 0, 1, 2 * 6 : This graph has the following strongly connected components: P_1: fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z) =#> F(Y, fold(F, X) Z) fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z) =#> fold(F, X) Z sum X =#> fold(add, 0) X prod X =#> fold(mul, s(0)) X By [Kop12, Thm. 7.31], we may replace any dependency pair problem (P_0, R_0, m, f) by (P_1, R_0, m, f). Thus, the original system is terminating if (P_1, R_0, minimal, formative) is finite. We consider the dependency pair problem (P_1, R_0, minimal, formative). This combination (P_1, R_0) has no formative rules! We will name the empty set of rules:R_1. By [Kop12, Thm. 7.17], we may replace the dependency pair problem (P_1, R_0, minimal, formative) by (P_1, R_1, minimal, formative). Thus, the original system is terminating if (P_1, R_1, minimal, formative) is finite. We consider the dependency pair problem (P_1, R_1, minimal, formative). We will use the reduction pair processor [Kop12, Thm. 7.16]. As the system is abstraction-simple and the formative flag is set, it suffices to find a tagged reduction pair [Kop12, Def. 6.70]. Thus, we must orient: fold(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) >? F(Y, fold(F, X, Z)) fold(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) >? fold(F, X, Z) sum(X) >? fold(add, 0, X) prod(X) >? fold(mul, s(0), X) We apply [Kop12, Thm. 6.75] and use the following argument functions: pi( prod(X) ) = #argfun-prod#(fold(mul, s(0), X)) pi( sum(X) ) = #argfun-sum#(fold(add, 0, X)) Since this representation is not advantageous for the higher-order recursive path ordering, we present the strict requirements in their unextended form, which is not problematic since for any F, s and substituion gamma: (F s)gamma beta-reduces to F(s)gamma.) We use a recursive path ordering as defined in [Kop12, Chapter 5]. Argument functions: [[0]] = _|_ [[add]] = _|_ [[mul]] = _|_ [[prod(x_1)]] = x_1 [[sum(x_1)]] = x_1 We choose Lex = {} and Mul = {#argfun-prod#, #argfun-sum#, @_{o -> o -> o}, @_{o -> o}, cons, fold, s}, and the following precedence: #argfun-prod# > #argfun-sum# > @_{o -> o -> o} = fold > @_{o -> o} > cons > s Taking the argument function into account, and fixing the greater / greater equal choices, the constraints can be denoted as follows: fold(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) > @_{o -> o}(@_{o -> o -> o}(F, Y), fold(F, X, Z)) fold(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) >= fold(F, X, Z) #argfun-sum#(fold(_|_, _|_, X)) >= fold(_|_, _|_, X) #argfun-prod#(fold(_|_, s(_|_), X)) >= fold(_|_, s(_|_), X) With these choices, we have: 1] fold(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) > @_{o -> o}(@_{o -> o -> o}(F, Y), fold(F, X, Z)) because [2], by definition 2] fold*(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) >= @_{o -> o}(@_{o -> o -> o}(F, Y), fold(F, X, Z)) because fold > @_{o -> o}, [3] and [8], by (Copy) 3] fold*(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) >= @_{o -> o -> o}(F, Y) because fold = @_{o -> o -> o}, fold in Mul, [4] and [5], by (Stat) 4] F >= F by (Meta) 5] cons(Y, Z) > Y because [6], by definition 6] cons*(Y, Z) >= Y because [7], by (Select) 7] Y >= Y by (Meta) 8] fold*(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) >= fold(F, X, Z) because fold in Mul, [4], [9] and [10], by (Stat) 9] X >= X by (Meta) 10] cons(Y, Z) > Z because [11], by definition 11] cons*(Y, Z) >= Z because [12], by (Select) 12] Z >= Z by (Meta) 13] fold(F, X, cons(Y, Z)) >= fold(F, X, Z) because [8], by (Star) 14] #argfun-sum#(fold(_|_, _|_, X)) >= fold(_|_, _|_, X) because [15], by (Star) 15] #argfun-sum#*(fold(_|_, _|_, X)) >= fold(_|_, _|_, X) because #argfun-sum# > fold, [16], [17] and [18], by (Copy) 16] #argfun-sum#*(fold(_|_, _|_, X)) >= _|_ by (Bot) 17] #argfun-sum#*(fold(_|_, _|_, X)) >= _|_ by (Bot) 18] #argfun-sum#*(fold(_|_, _|_, X)) >= X because [19], by (Select) 19] fold(_|_, _|_, X) >= X because [20], by (Star) 20] fold*(_|_, _|_, X) >= X because [21], by (Select) 21] X >= X by (Meta) 22] #argfun-prod#(fold(_|_, s(_|_), X)) >= fold(_|_, s(_|_), X) because [23], by (Star) 23] #argfun-prod#*(fold(_|_, s(_|_), X)) >= fold(_|_, s(_|_), X) because #argfun-prod# > fold, [24], [25] and [27], by (Copy) 24] #argfun-prod#*(fold(_|_, s(_|_), X)) >= _|_ by (Bot) 25] #argfun-prod#*(fold(_|_, s(_|_), X)) >= s(_|_) because #argfun-prod# > s and [26], by (Copy) 26] #argfun-prod#*(fold(_|_, s(_|_), X)) >= _|_ by (Bot) 27] #argfun-prod#*(fold(_|_, s(_|_), X)) >= X because [28], by (Select) 28] fold(_|_, s(_|_), X) >= X because [29], by (Star) 29] fold*(_|_, s(_|_), X) >= X because [30], by (Select) 30] X >= X by (Meta) By the observations in [Kop12, Sec. 6.6], this reduction pair suffices; we may thus replace the dependency pair problem (P_1, R_1, minimal, formative) by (P_2, R_1, minimal, formative), where P_2 consists of: fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z) =#> fold(F, X) Z sum X =#> fold(add, 0) X prod X =#> fold(mul, s(0)) X Thus, the original system is terminating if (P_2, R_1, minimal, formative) is finite. We consider the dependency pair problem (P_2, R_1, minimal, formative). We place the elements of P in a dependency graph approximation G (see e.g. [Kop12, Thm. 7.27, 7.29], as follows: * 0 : 0 * 1 : 0 * 2 : 0 This graph has the following strongly connected components: P_3: fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z) =#> fold(F, X) Z By [Kop12, Thm. 7.31], we may replace any dependency pair problem (P_2, R_1, m, f) by (P_3, R_1, m, f). Thus, the original system is terminating if (P_3, R_1, minimal, formative) is finite. We consider the dependency pair problem (P_3, R_1, minimal, formative). We apply the subterm criterion with the following projection function: nu(fold) = 3 Thus, we can orient the dependency pairs as follows: nu(fold(F, X) cons(Y, Z)) = cons(Y, Z) |> Z = nu(fold(F, X) Z) By [FuhKop19, Thm. 61], we may replace a dependency pair problem (P_3, R_1, minimal, f) by ({}, R_1, minimal, f). By the empty set processor [Kop12, Thm. 7.15] this problem may be immediately removed. As all dependency pair problems were succesfully simplified with sound (and complete) processors until nothing remained, we conclude termination. +++ Citations +++ [FuhKop19] C. Fuhs, and C. Kop. A static higher-order dependency pair framework. In Proceedings of ESOP 2019, 2019. [Kop12] C. Kop. Higher Order Termination. PhD Thesis, 2012.